[John Milton Binckley, “The Death Penalty.” The Lakeside Monthly. Vol. IX. January to June, 1873. Chicago: F. F. Browne and Company, 1873. Part 3: pages 331-333. Extra paragraph breaks made for easier reading.]
A little reflection shows,
then, that this innovation, great as might be its consequences, would be an innovation
mainly of form, and that not a whit more than necessary to remove obstructions
of the acknowledged truth of the matter, as the age sees it, everywhere but the
very place where it is wanted — in court. But to abolish or seriously modify
the jury system, while, to some, seemingly a comparatively slight change, could
not be rated below a fundamental revolution of political government. The
strange rashness in this matter seems to result from inattention to the nature
of jury trial.
[Many thanks to William Myers, Mary Davy and Sally Young for their ongoing research collaboration.]
What
would be the effect? Many, rashly undervaluing the reasons of the thing, will
say it is "honoring" the murderer. But will it tend to deter murder?
[T]hat is the question. We think it would, because juries, judges, governors
and the public would conceive of the execution without those harrowing and
dreadful incident: which now render a refined or a sympathetic man unwilling to
permit anybody to be. The murderer himself, devoted to a decent death, in the
very tokens of sympathy he might receive would realize his doom; for as a
doomed and not a threatened man, he would be tenderly pitied, forgiven and
favored as he ought to be. A man devoted to death is not necessarily a man to
be saved from death if possible, even if he is guiltless. Brothers in arms, willing
to die for each other, make no effort to keep each other out of appointed danger.
It is not that the civilized heart of the age revolts, that a man — at least, a
bad and dangerous man — should die, but that he should be passed through the
barbaric and shameful gibbet - tableau, that abominable anachronism of our
magistracy.
A
second method of increasing a sense of the certainty of punishment is to
solemnly enact, in the statute of murder, that in every case of homicide the
person who did the killing shall be deemed and held to have devoted himself to
death, and to have invoked the instrumentality of the law for the execution of
his doom, by virtue of his act of murder; with provisions for the case of
misadventure, sudden heat, etc. The indictment, then, should simply raise an
issue of inquest as to the facts, and of judgment as to what might be adduced
to rebut the statutory presumption that, by the killing, the prisoner had
adjudged himself to death. This suggestion is novel, but not so radical as it
may appear. It would leave a prosecution subject to every principle of
procedure that now exists, except a few mischievous and perplexing fictions.
One of these is, that the offence is against the State, or, as in England,
against the Queen.
"Vengeance
is mine," was said by the King of kings and of queens. The State has no
warrant in modern ethics for assuming to restore the equilibrium of eternal
justice disturbed by a murder. She is in no just sense vindicatory, but only
conservative. She must protect the living, not avenge the dead. For this
necessity, she may put a man to death. But that it is, after all, in execution
of his own self-condemnation, is apparent from this: that if the State had
neglected to make and provide a statute against murder, it could not pretend,
legally, to the right to touch a hair of a confessed murderer's head.
It
is, therefore, solely in virtue of its warning him that he cannot murder
another without, by his own act, voluntarily procuring himself to be murdered,
that the State acquires a right to use its machinery of justice; and not in
virtue of the injury it has sustained at the hands of the murderer. This is but
a corollary of the law itself, and therefore within the law to-day.
The
practical operation of thus altering the issue in a capital case would cut off
incidentally nearly all of that hitherto invincible cobwebbery which now
renders the common sense of the facts and the sober logic of the law almost
inaccessible to bench and bar, witnesses and spectators, in a murder trial.
The
prisoner himself can have no clear idea of his crime, as against society. If to
this charge were added the suggestion above mentioned for rendering a review
inoperative unless it should touch the real question of guilt or innocence, we
cannot but think a murder trial would almost necessarily result justly, and the
sentence go into effect inexorably, because from the murder to the execution
the whole public could see the rationale
of the case.
But
again, the solemn promulgation of the principle that on his own hands was his
own blood, would strike the heart of the man compassing a murder with a now
unknown terror of crushing simplicity. It would but formulate the truth as it
stands to-day — unrecognized by law, and therefore obscured by fictions — in
every conscience in the land. No man with bloody hands would hope to make head
against that simple and awful truth. No longer could he count on that powerful
and noble prompting of the heart of man to side with the weaker; for no longer
would his case strike the public imagination with the purely illusory but
affecting figure of a solitary and miserable man at war for his life with the
huge and unfeeling State. It would then appear, what it really is, an inquiry
into the truth of a case, of which ulterior results have been already
determined by the party himself, unless investigation lifts the gloom lowering
from the sky of natural justice.
[Many thanks to William Myers, Mary Davy and Sally Young for their ongoing research collaboration.]
No comments:
Post a Comment
Commentaires